THE HUFFINGTON POST--SCIENCE 29 January 2014
Famed astrophysicist Stephen Hawking has shaken up the popular science world with his newest study about the basic nature of black holes, but is his idea revolutionary? Some scientists aren't convinced.
Hawking's new black hole study — entitled "Information Preservation and Weather Forecasting for Black Holes" — was published Jan. 22 through the preprint journal arXiv.org and has not yet undergone the peer review vetting process typical for academic papers. It attempts to solve a paradox surrounding the basic building blocks of how the universe works.
"Hawking's paper is short and does not have a lot of detail, so it is not clear what his precise picture is, or what the justification is," Joseph Polchinski of the Kavli Institute wrote in an email to SPACE.com. [The Strangest Black Holes in the Universe]
Current theories about black holes hinge upon what's known as the "firewall paradox." This paradox pits Einstein's theory of general relativity against quantum theory in the context of a black hole. The paradox, developed by Polchinski and colleagues about two years ago, is based upon a thought experiment about would happen to a person if he or she fell into a black hole.
Richard H. Brodhead, the New York TIMES, 23 June 2002, on a "black hole" I alone had the instruments to detect."
Richard Brodhead,
Andrew Delbanco, and Elizabeth Schultz in 2002 expressed their high-minded
doubts as to the existence of The Isle of
the Cross in 1853 and a volume Melville called Poems in 1860. I had merely surmised that Melville completed a book
in 1853, said Brodhead, by then the dean of Yale College, in the June 23, 2002,
New York Times. My surmises went on: “Parker is also convinced that
Melville prepared a volume of poems in 1860 that failed to be published. If
this is so, a stretch that had seemed empty of literary strivings was instead a
time of new effort and new failure—a black hole Parker alone has the
instruments to detect” (13). Andrew Delbanco, the Levi Professor in the
Humanities at Columbia University, known to be a biographer-in-waiting, in the New Republic (September 2002) declared
that I was “amazingly certain” (34) of my own conclusions, such as Melville’s
completion of a book in 1853 (merely a surmise, he said) and Poems in 1860 (it “was never
published—and it is a surmise that Melville ever wrote it”). Delbanco warned
that my certainty of my conclusions meant that the second volume, like the first,
“must be used with caution” (34). Elizabeth Schultz in the Common Review (Winter 2002) gave a further punitive twist to the
accusations: “Parker also reads betrayal and despair into the disappearance of
two manuscripts, which he contends Melville completed—a novel, putatively
titled The Isle of the Cross, and his
first collection of poems” (45). As
Backscheider says, “For an academic to be accused of ‘making up things’ . . .
is the most serious charge that can be levelled against him or her and may discredit
that person forever” (xix). I may die still widely discredited and shamed in
print and on the Internet by the false accusations of these three Melville
critics, but starting in 2007 I have been trying to make the truth known, even
at the cost of some barely perceptible repetitions.
In dismissing me as the sole
adventurer to bring back a report from that “black hole,” Brodhead was
dismissing three quarters of a century of scholarship. To be blunt, Brodhead
was acting as if the scholars from Minnigerode on had never labored in the
archives, never published their discoveries, never rejoiced when later workers
added their supplementary findings. I alone “had the instruments to detect” Poems, so I had fantasized it. I was an
unreliable biographer, and the scholars I had revered and built upon had never
existed. I have talked about Brodhead’s blindness to human agony. He, Delbanco,
and Schultz also display here something worse: blindness to human existence,
blindness to the working lives of remarkable scholars. They dismiss scholars
like Thorp and Hayford as if they had never existed. I emphasize this again to
make clear the wreckage Charles N. Feidelson made of scholarship at Yale and
other Ivy League universities and the contempt for human beings which his
principles encouraged.
Does
such slander in the mainstream media matter, except to the person whose
reputation is being damaged and to the children and grandchildren of the
now-dead scholars whose memories are erased? Yes, for such false proclamations
still confuse the innocent critic who reads the slanderers but not the
scholarship. Apparently influenced by one or more of these critics, Edgar A.
Dryden in 2004 (207 n. 2) said, “Hershel Parker argues convincingly that
Melville tried unsuccessfully to publish a book of poems in 1860.” No, no! In
my biography there is no such argument.
Why would I argue something everyone knew? Instead, I merely make a fresh
presentation of the long-familiar evidence that when Melville sailed from
Boston with his brother in 1860 he left behind in manuscript a volume of poetry
which he expected to be published in New York in his absence. I had new things
to say about his reading epics on the voyage and other matters, but not much
new about the volume of poems except some attention to the evidence of its
length.
What’s at stake with the denial of The Isle of the Cross and Poems is a true sense of the trajectory
of Melville’s career, in which The Isle
of the Cross comes between Pierre
and the first stories and in which the lectures precede Poems and Battle-Pieces
follows it. A responsible critic would have dismissed Baym’s efforts to keep
something like Weaver’s unsupported theories before new generations of critics.
A responsible critic would have been open to ways that Pierre as a psychological novel grows out of the examinations of
the workings of the mind in Moby-Dick. Such
a critic might have looked at ways in which Melville’s suggestions to Hawthorne
about the Agatha Hatch material might seem to continue or develop beyond his
techniques in Pierre. Instead of
writing about “Bartleby” as if it followed Pierre,
such a critic would use all the available evidence to speculate responsibly
about how Melville might have grown, in style, psychology, and intellect, in
the process of brooding about the Agatha Hatch story in the fall of 1852 and of
writing the lost The Isle of the Cross
from mid-December 1852 till late May 1853. Similarly, a responsible critic
would take account of how Melville might have grown as a poet in the process of
writing the lost Poems from 1857 or
1858 until May 1860. No one can think responsibly about Battle-Pieces (1866), John
Marr (1888), and Timoleon (1891),
or about the 1876 Clarel, without
taking into account the book of poetry which Melville was not able to print in
1860.
No comments:
Post a Comment